[FRIAM] two books

lrudolph at meganet.net lrudolph at meganet.net
Sun Dec 9 08:27:49 EST 2018


Jon Zingale writes, in relevant part:

> In modern mathematics, one encounters categories whose
> `points` have an internal structure which can be more
> complicated than one's initial intuition would provide.
> There is a sense that what the interested physicist is doing
> by exploring the duality is attempting to understand the nature
> of 'physical points'. How is a physical point like a point in
> Euclidean geometry? To what extent can there be a consistent
> formal description which matches our knowledge of these points?
>
> Perhaps from some phenomenological perspective, we should
> understand these physical points as founding all experience
> regarding points and waves. After all, assuming the present
> quantum mechanical presentation, all of the classical
> experiences of  wave-like nature and particle-like nature
> are derived from interactions of these underlying primitive
> objects.

Here, modulo reformatting for ASCII e-mail, is part of one section of one
of my editorial chapters ("Functions of Structure in Mathematics and
Modeling") in my widely unread edited book "Qualitative Mathematics for
the Social Sciences" (Routledge, 2013; get your local libraries to order
dozens!), which (at least) obliquely talks to the issues Jon raises here,
and handles the issue of "more complicated than one's initial intuition"
somewhat head-on (though probably pitched above the head of most of the
social scientists who were the purported audience).

===begin===

ON MATHEMATICAL SPACES

The preceding discussion of projective planes provides not just explicit
examples of how set-theoretical definitions are used mathematically, but
also many examples (there not drawn explicitly to attention) of how (parts
of) such definitions can acquire or give meaning in the course of their
mathematical and para-mathematical interactions with other structures
(some mathematical but having definitions that remain out of attention,
others ‘in the world’ and defined—if at all—non-mathematically). In this
section I pick up just one of those dropped threads.

Many mathematical structures have been called ‘spaces’ (usually with some
modifier) since at least the discovery of non-Euclidean
geometries—notably, the real projective plane RP2 and the real hyperbolic
plane—early in the 19th century, and well before there were any
set-theoretical “foundations of mathematics”. By mid 20th century,
mathematical ‘spaces’ were common not only in geometry but in algebra
(‘vector spaces’), mathematical analysis (‘Hilbert spaces’, ‘Banach
spaces’, ‘Hardy spaces’, and many other kinds of vector spaces with extra
structure, as well as ‘metric spaces’ and ‘measure
spaces’), abstract algebra (‘representation spaces’, ‘prime ideal
spaces’), probability theory (‘probability spaces’), mathematical physics
(‘phase spaces’), and especially topology—the quintessential mathematics
of the 20th century—in its many manifestations: point-set, combinatorial,
algebraic, geometric, and differential. No single strictly mathematical
property is shared by these many kinds of ‘spaces’, but mathematicians in
general seem content to agree that the metaphor is broadly appropriate.

Typically, when mathematicians call some mathematical structure S a space
(here to be called a mathematical space in the hopes of averting
confusion), they understand it to share, in some sense and to some degree,
the following rather general pre-mathematical properties of the ordinary
space of our daily experience. [Footnote 15: Many presuppositions are
packed into the phrase “the ordinary space of our daily experience” and
its variants, and most if not all of them are probably unjustifiably
broad, particularly if “daily experience” is read so as to naïvely ignore
or tendentiously suppress the considerable role of linguistic framings
(cultural and sub-cultural, semi-permanent and evanescent) in that
“experience”. Still, the phrase and its variants have a reasonably well
delimited denotation that is widely understood (until it is examined
overly closely), so I take the risk of using it here.]
(1) A mathematical space is like a box that can ‘contain’ other sorts of
‘things’.
(2) A mathematical space is like a stage on which various ‘events’ can
‘happen’ (e.g., ‘things’ can ‘move’) in the course of time. [Footnote 16:
Somewhat confusingly, “time” is very often thought of as a mathematical
space by mathematicians. See Chap. 10, p. 308, and Rudolph (2006a).]
Properties (1) and (2) are essentially extrinsic to a candidate S for
‘spacehood’: they depend almost entirely not on what S is but on how S is
used.[Footnote 17: In particular, one and the same mathematical structure
S can be called a ‘space’ or not depending on the use to which it is being
put.] In contrast, a third general property is chiefly intrinsic.
(3) A mathematical space ‘has extent’, and can (usually) be ‘subdivided’;
a ‘piece’ of a mathematical space, though (usually) of smaller ‘extent’,
still has in its own right the quality of being a mathematical space.
Naturally, the interpretation of (3) depends on the meaning given to
‘extent’, ‘piece’, etc., and in that sense it is somewhat extrinsic.

What mathematicians typically try hard not to do, when calling a
mathematical structure a ‘space’, is to attribute to that structure other
properties of ordinary space that are not explicitly demanded by the
context in which the structure is being used. Model-making scientists, be
they physical, life, or social scientists, are often less fastidious when
they adopt the metaphor of ‘space’ for mathematical models in their own
disciplines: in contrast with mathematicians, they tend to incorporate
into their models not only the general properties (1)–(3) of ordinary
space, but also some or all of the following special properties.
(4) Ordinary space has (or can have imposed upon it) metric properties,
including (but not limited to) numerical measures of distance, area,
volume, and other forms of ‘extent’; a mathematical space need not.
(5) Ordinary space has (or can have imposed upon it) geometric properties,
such as notions of ‘straightness’ and ‘curvature’, ‘convexity’ and
‘concavity’, ‘collinearity’, ‘congruence’, and the like; a mathematical
space need not.
(6) Ordinary space has properties of continuity, homogeneity (i.e.,
indistinguishability among locations per se) and isotropy (i.e.,
indistinguishability among directions per se) [Footnote 18: Or, at least,
horizontal directions are (among themselves, ignoring their ‘contents’)
indistinguishable in ordinary space; as Shepard (1992, p. 500) points out,
gravity makes verticality salient for surface-dwellers (or rather, for
those surface-dwellers that live above the “nanoscale” at which van der
Waals forces, Brownian motion, etc., have effects much stronger than those
of gravity).]; a mathematical space need not. [Footnote 19: In this
connection, it is almost incredible—to a mathematician educated in the
second half of the 20th century—to read that, for instance, Bertrand
Russell (1896)
    [i]n his first published paper [...] analyses the axioms of Euclidean
    geometry [...] and finds that some of the axioms are certainly true,
    and in particular a priori true, “for their denial would involve logical
    and philosophical absurdities” (p. 3). He classifies for instance the
    homogeneity of space as a priori true, the “want of homogeneity and
    passivity is ... absurd: no philosopher has ever thrown doubt, so far
    as I know, on these two properties of empty space [...].” (Lakatos, 1962,
    p. 168; the unbracketed ellipsis points, and the italics, are Lakatos’s.)
Moreover, Russell (1896, p. 1) purports to come to his conclusions even
though
    we are not concerned with the correspondence of Geometry with fact;
    we are concerned with Geometry simply as a body of reasoning, the
    conditions of whose possibility we wish to examine [...] we have to do
    with the conception of space in its most finished and elaborated form,
    after thought has done its utmost in transforming the intuitional data.
Probably the best (though very difficult) course of action for the modern
mathematician, incredulous in the face of what appears to be such an
enormous blind spot, would be to take an appropriate modification of
Stallings’s advice (quoted on p. 64), and ‘cultivate techniques leading to
the abandonment’ of one’s own mechanisms for maintaining one’s own (surely
numerous) blind spots.]
(7) In ordinary space, a ‘point’ is atomic, with no internal structure; in
many important examples of mathematical spaces, each ‘point’ is a complex
structure in its own right.

Although the policy of endowing mathematical spaces used as models with
some or all of the special properties (4)–(7) has often been harmless, and
occasionally useful, in the natural sciences, I see no evidence that it
has often been useful (and some evidence that it has sometimes been
harmful) in the human sciences. In any case, mathematicians typically see
the denial, to a given mathematical space, of some or all of these special
properties—especially (7)—as entirely normal, and frequently commendable.
[Footnote 20: Euclid’s Definition 1 states that “a point is that which has
no parts”. But, e.g., in all the definitions of RP2, at least some
points—being sets with two elements—have non-trivial, if meager,
mereologies. A class of examples of mathematical spaces having far more
radically “non-atomic” points than those of RP2 is that of configuration
spaces of (mathematical or physical) systems of various sorts. In a
configuration space, each point is a single configuration of the entire
system. See Wehrle, Kaiser, Schmidt, and Scherer (2000) for an application
to the dynamics of human affect that—in effect—constitutes a partial
exploration of a mathematical space of “schematic facial expressions
consisting entirely of theoretically postulated facial muscle
configurations” (p. 105).]

===end===

I guess one thing not mentioned there, which occurs to me as I reread the
text I quoted from Jon, is the importance of keeping in mind (if not
necessarily always at the front of one's mind, that is, in active
attention [<---notice the metaphorical "spatialization" inherent in the
idiomatic uses of "at the front" and "in"]) that which "objects" are
"underlying primitive objects" is not necessarily, and perhaps necessarily
NOT, a fact about the system being modeled, but rather a fact about the
model.

Cheers,

Lee Rudolph




More information about the Friam mailing list